“I was always dreaming about very powerful
people - dictators and things like that. I was just always impressed by people
who could be remembered for hundreds of years, or even, like Jesus, be for
thousands of years remembered."
Arnold Schwarzenegger
Classical Greek ethical and political philosophy is ultimately divisible
into two main streams.
The first is the Platonic idealism with its Pythagorean foundations.
The
second is the Aristotelian ‘realism’ with its biological foundations. This
means there are two main metaphysics of man, which ultimately feed into the
idea of a good life.
Before the rise of the
Athenian philosophers there had already been the idea of a life devoted to
contemplation, as found in the Pre-Socratic philosophers. When Aristotle writes
in the Ethics that the best life includes contemplation he is referring to such
people and their lives. These philosophical lives were rare.
However, during the
growth of Athens in the “Golden Age” a life of the gentleman evolved, which
included a life dedicated to the polis, and to an active social life in the
community. (The Greeks had no word for ‘social’ only for ‘political’ based on
the idea of a special space, a polis) The life of the gentleman was a life of
politics, a life of leisure and included both the private life of the home and
personal affairs as well as the public life of the city-state and public
affairs.
In Plato, we find a
celebration of the philosophical life over and above the political life, since
the philosopher kings would be forced into politics, which is below them.
Socrates in various passages discusses how he does not have the time for
politics in reference to the public sphere, and how he is a terrible husband,
in reference to the private sphere. The idea of the philosophical life as found
in the Pre-Socratics is held as the best. It is also the base of Epicurus’s
philosophy and therefore was influential on the Stoic ideas of the good life.
Therefore, when
Aristotle in the Ethics attempts to discuss the nature of the good life, he
says that while there are many opinions, the best life is the one dedicated to
philosophy, but for Aristotle this would necessarily include the political
life. The idea of a contemplative life
in opposition to an active life is not in Aristotle, but was a creation of
later interpreters. The Latin concepts of vita-activa and vita-contemplativa
are not in Aristotle; instead, Aristotle has two major distinctions.
The first is the opposition of a
life dedicated to philosophy with lives dedicated to indulgence in the forms of
pleasure or honour or wealth. Aristotle is distinguishing between a life
dedicated to leisure or a life still caught up in the world of labour and
necessity. That is the difference.
The second is the opposition of leisure
used for contemplation as found in the Ethics for those who have the components
and leisure for the appreciation of the arts in the Politics as the proper end
for the gentleman which he calls noble leisure.
For Plato, immortality of the
soul meant that a human life of virtue and appeasing the gods meant a happy
after life. Therefore, for Plato, the philosophical life, concerned with
private affairs led to immortality. Leisure in this sense is the attitude one
takes towards the private life and the use of free time for the sake of the
soul but is not connected with the public affairs.
However, for Aristotle there was
no immortal soul. The ‘political life’ was the proper use of leisure and this
meant a life that included by necessity the private life, but also included the
public life. BECAUSE since the human was mortal, the only chance for any sense
of immortality was through great works and deeds, so that one could be
remembered and honored after death.
CONCLUSION: Leisure
is the path to immortality. In a less dramatic way, leisure is the space for
necessary components of the good life such as artistic, athletic and minor-political
honors in times of peace.